Kant's Ethics
Sandra LaFave
The Good Will The right motive is “to do the right thing”, “to do one’s duty”, “to respect the moral law.” A rational being who consistently has the right motive has what Kant calls a Good Will. Nothing is more important for morality than having a good will. According to Kant, a rational being with a Good Will automatically does its duty. Why? Read on.
Why Consequentialism is Wrong First consider what would motivate you if you had a Good Will. You’d do your duty simply because it’s your duty. You wouldn’t expect a reward. You wouldn’t expect to make yourself happy or give yourself pleasure. You’d want to do your duty simply because it’s your duty. In other words, all consequences — any pleasure or happiness that might result (or any pain and misery that might be avoided) — are irrelevant. Duty is what makes you good; it’s not what makes you (or anyone else) happy. It’s not what satisfies natural inclinations to attain pleasure or happiness. So part of having a Good Will is making your moral decisions without considering whether they would create happiness or pleasure, or avoid pain. Consider the same point another way. You’re a person. You’re not an animal. Animals seek the fulfillment of natural inclinations; they automatically seek natural goods because they can’t act any other way. But rational beings are more than animals. Unlike animals, rational beings can reason; rational beings can contemplate alternative acts, and evaluate behavior in accordance with principles of reason. If you’re a consequentialist, you undervalue yourself; you place yourself on the same moral level as animals. Consequentialism says you should seek whatever makes for the best consequences; but that’s what your instinctive, animal self would do anyway. So a consequentialist theory like utilitarianism isn’t a moral theory at all, since it doesn’t recognize any essential difference between humans and animals. A rational being with a Good Will thus won’t be a consequentialist. For a rational being with a Good Will, the consequences won’t matter in the determination of whether acts are moral or immoral. A Good Will is thus “purified”; it has no inferior motives, such as desire for pleasure, happiness, or self-interest. Categorical and Hypothetical Imperatives Kant explains the nature of moral commands using his distinction between categorical imperatives and hypothetical imperatives. An imperative is a command. A hypothetical imperative is a command that applies if you want to attain a particular outcome. The following conditional sentence expresses a hypothetical imperative: “If you want to see the new Star Wars movie on opening day in San Jose, then you must stand in line for hours.” Must you obey this imperative? Must you stand in line for hours? Only if you have the relevant desire to see the new Star Wars movie on opening day in San Jose. If you don’t care, you can ignore the imperative. Kant says moral imperatives are never conditional. They are never hypothetical. For Kant, moral imperatives are always categorical, i.e., absolutely binding regardless of personal interest or desire. What you care about simply doesn’t matter. Your duty is your duty, and you must do it whether or not you want to. (That’s why a Good Will is so vital for Kant: a Good Will wants to.) Nothing exempts a moral agent from the demands of moral duty. Why Bad Acts Are Bad Kant analyzes evil as a kind of logical error, or mistake in reasoning. A contradiction is the worst logical error. It would obviously be a contradiction for a rational being to say “Every rational being should do X, except me.” Contradiction of this form is called special pleading. When rational beings will to do bad things, they want a contradiction: they want everybody else to do the right thing, because that's exactly what makes their wrongdoing possible. For example, the liar wants everyone else to tell the truth; if everyone lied, no one would believe the liar's lie. So the liar in effect is willing a contradiction: “Every rational being should tell the truth, except me.” This is special pleading: wanting the rule to apply to everyone AND not to me. Such a contradiction is a failure of universalizability. Categorical Imperative — Universalizability Formulations It follows for Kant that reason alone motivates a Good Will (one that is rational and discounts consequences). As Kant puts it, “As I have deprived the will of every impulse which could arise to it from obedience to any law [of nature], there remains nothing but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general, which alone is to serve the will as a principle.” In other words, a rational being of Good Will wants its actions to conform to universalizable principles of action.[1] For Kant, all rational beings — all beings capable of formulating maxims and recognizing contradiction — would agree with and endorse actions that spring from any single individual rational being with a Good Will, because non-contradiction is a universal law for rational beings. Therefore, the rational being of Good Will uses the Categorical Imperative to evaluate its actions: “Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” Or, "Act as if the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature."[2] To discover your duty, see if your maxim accords with this rule.
Why a Rational Being with a Good Will is Never Bad Desires for pleasure, happiness, or self-interest are inferior
motives, since such desires are always at the bottom of special pleading:
I want to make an exception for my own case because I think I’ll benefit
— get some natural good — as a result. Special pleading is a kind of
irrationality.
Desires for pleasure, happiness, or self-interest thus are impediments
to perfect rationality. But a Good Will has been “purified” of such inferior motives.
A Good Will has no such inferior motives. A Good Will thus never falls
into the fallacy of special pleading. A Good Will’s maxims are invariably
universalizable without contradiction, because the Good Will has no
impediments
to reasoning well. So a rational being with a Good Will always acts rightly,
in accordance with the Categorical Imperative, and thus in accordance
with duty. In other words, for a rational being with a Good Will, being
moral and being rational (logical) – and being fully human – are the same
thing. Why a Good Will
Respects
Rational Beings Most things have only conditional value; that is, they are
valuable only as means to an end, whose value is greater. Ultimately,
to avoid infinite regress, something must exist of absolute value. Now,
anything a rational being can have
or get has only conditional value, because
it merely satisfies an inclination of the rational being. But rational
beings themselves are different. If not for rational beings, nothing would
have value at all. Therefore, it is only through rational beings that
value itself even exists. Therefore, rational beings, because they are
the sources of value, cannot themselves have value. Their value is absolute
and supreme. Therefore, rational beings command respect simply because
they are rational beings. As Kant puts it: “Rational nature is an end
in itself.” |