Thinking Critically
About the "Subjective"/"Objective" Distinction
Sandra LaFave
The words "subjective" and "
objective" cause lots of confusion. Their misuse is responsible for subjectivism
in ethics. Ethical subjectivism is the view that moral judgements are nothing but
statements or expressions of personal opinion or feeling and thus that moral
judgements cannot be supported or refuted by reason. Careless use of the
terms "subjective" and "objective" also leads to odd views in metaphysics,
e.g., the denial of material reality (idealism); and
odd views in epistemology, e.g., the claim that all statements are equally warranted.
In other words, if you're
careless about how you handle the concepts of subjectivity and objectivity, you
can end up saying there's no such thing as morality, reality, or truth!
The ordinary non-philosophical (i.e.,
oversimplified) view is that the word "subjective" is the complete
opposite (negation or contradictory) of the word "objective." If something is subjective, it's not
objective; if something is objective, it's not subjective. "Subjective" is
thought to mean "from someones point of view." "
Objective" means "not just from someones point of
view." An objective matter is one that everyone (who is sane, rational, and
appropriately informed) will agree about. "Subjectivity" connotes
lack of objectivity. Ethical subjectivism is the view that since we
cant be "objective" about morality, morality must be purely
"subjective."
Furthermore, on the ordinary non-philosophical view, "subjective"
goes with words like "belief" or "opinion." The idea is that
subjective matters are not certain. "Objective," on the other hand,
means "certain" or "factual." "Objective"
matters are those that can be measured or quantified. For example, the answers to
questions such as "How many desks are in this room?" and "What
is the current temperature in this room?" would be objective. Note that these
questions have precise mathematical answers, and anyone with access to the
appropriate properly-working measuring devices would agree what those answers
are.
In this essay, I am going to critically analyze this ordinary oversimplified
(problematic) view, so let's recap it now:
This oversimplified way of making the
distinction leads to philosophical trouble.
Consider your experience of a headache versus your experience of the Eiffel
Tower. Naturally, you have your own personal private "subjective" experience of
the headache, and nobody else can have your headache for you. So, in one of the usual
(oversimplified)
senses of "subjective", all
headaches are subjective.
But people tend to say furthermore that "subjective" and "objective" are logical
opposites in the strongest sense: they are negations or contradictories of each other.
This means that if X is subjective, it can't be objective, and if X is
objective it can't be subjective. In other words, people mistakenly think everything
has to be EITHER subjective OR objective. This leads to startling consequences.
You have a headache. You feel it, and nobody else does, so you
say it's "subjective" (private). But look at the other notions that go with "subjective": if
its subjective, its just your opinion.
But opinions have no standing — so why should the doctor believe you when
you say you have a headache? The doctor doesn't feel your headache;
it's just your opinion — and you might find yourself agreeing that
you can't be "objective" about your
headache. And since your headache isn't objective, it isn't
really REAL at all!
The headache is "really" just in your mind. (This is the philosophy
behind Christian Science.)
Now of course you could apply this very same
reasoning to your experience of the Eiffel Tower. There you are in Paris, looking at
the Eiffel Tower, and you think, "Gee, no one else is having this precise experience
of the Eiffel Tower, so this experience of mine is just as subjective as my
headache!" (And that wouldn't be wrong, of course, in a way; it's true that no one
else has your precise experience of the Eiffel Tower either.)
But if all you really know
is that you had a subjective experience of seeing the Eiffel Tower, and
thats all anyone ever has, why say the Eiffel Tower or anything
exists objectively, independently of observers? But we do (at least most of us do). We think emotions
and pains are real AND we also think physical things are real. Yet when some people get "philosophical" and
begin thinking of all experience as "subjective" (not only their experiences of pains
and feelings but also their experiences of so-called "physical" things), they can't then be certain
anything exists "objectively," independently of their experiences. All they "know" are
their experiences, which are "subjective," and thus just "opinion".
Because of confusion about subjectivity and objectivity, people get led
down the philosophical road to skepticism and metaphysical idealism and solipsism.
Metaphysical idealism is the view that there is no
reality independently of people's minds — in other words,
according to metaphysical idealism,
so-called "physical" things don't really exist at all.
Nothing exists independently of our experiences, and since
our experiences are private, they count as "mental" and thus "in our minds",
so nothing exists independently of our minds. (I say "our" minds, but of course, a real
idealist would object to this locution, since one consequence
of metaphysical idealism is that other people exist only in my mind; i.e., there are no other minds
except mine — that's what philosophers call solipsism.)
Metaphysical idealism
was popular in philosophy in the early 1800's, and re-emerged in the late 20th century
as deconstruction or post-modernism. Once you understand
how most people oversimplify the terms "subjective" and "objective",
it's not hard to understand
why good-hearted people get snookered by
metaphysical idealism. Here's a typical argument.
(Premise 1) All my experiences are metaphysically subjective (i.e., no one else
has my unique experiences; all my experiences are from my unique point of view).
(Premise 2) "Subjective" is the opposite of "objective". If X is subjective,
it can't be objective, and vice-versa.
(Premise 3) If my experiences are metaphysically subjective, then by Premise 2,
any statements I
make about my experiences must be
epistemologically subjective — they
are "merely" my beliefs, or my opinions. By Premise 2, nothing
metaphysically subjective can suddenly acquire the prestige of "objectivity".
For any X, if X is subjective, X stays subjective.
(Conclusion) But — hang on to your seats, now, this is the big "insight" —
Premises 1 and 3 are true of everyone! Whoever you are
(Mother Teresa, Einstein, Charles Manson, Hitler, Neo, Trinity, etc.),
you have access only to
your experiences ("your reality") and no one else's,
and whatever you say, it's just your opinion ("your truth").
We simply can't be objective.
There is no Objective Reality or Objective Truth.
Reality and truth differ for everyone, and always will.
This argument gets a lot of support in this age of Political Correctness.
If we all have only our limited points of view, nobody has THE truth.
For too
long now, some people have disrespected others' opinions in the name of
"THE truth". But this argument shows that the "Truth Fairy" doesn't exist,
and it's time all the European/male/imperialist/capitalist/Christian folks learned
a little proper humility.
There's nothing
special about anyone's point of view;
everybody's point of view is equally correct. Sound familiar?
We have a tangled web here.
Confusion about the
subjective-objective distinction might lead you to philosophical positions that are
completely at odds with your ordinary beliefs and practices. Philosophy is supposed
to clarify, enlighten, explain, etc.; the ordinary senses of "subjective" and "objective"
merely confuse and mystify!
Contemporary philosophers conclude that something is very wrong with the ordinary
simple-minded opposition of "subjective" and "objective."
Let's start untangling the obviously less
plausible parts of this argument.
First, metaphysical idealism seems unbelievable. It's more than a little odd to doubt
the existence of a world external to your experience.
When you live your life,
you do seem persistently to ACT as
though there is a world independent of your mind a world you didn't make
up and that you don't control.
Philosophical pragmatists say (I think correctly) that you don't
really believe any proposition if it has no effect on your choices.
For example, if you really believed that tables and chairs didn't exist,
you wouldn't walk around them. You do walk around them. So you're
not really skeptical about their existence.
A lot of people might say, "Well, you can't prove metaphysical
idealism is false,
can you?". (These are maybe the sort of people who think The Matrix has deep
philosophical significance.)
Arguments like that are pretty lame, though; they commit the fallacy of appeal to ignorance.
You appeal to ignorance when your only premise in support of a claim is that
you or your opponent can't show the claim is false, i.e., you are ignorant of
any evidence that would disprove it. But that kind of ignorance doesn't prove anything.
Think about it: I can't prove the universe didn't come into existence five minutes ago,
complete with "historical"
records and "memories," but the fact that I can't prove it's false doesn't
make it true, or even plausible. I can't prove there isn't an invisible elephant (with no
odor or any sensible properties)
in my backyard. But if I seriously concluded on the basis of my ignorance
of reasons for disproof that there were such an elephant, you
would not say "Ms. LaFave, you are such a deep thinker"; you would say "Ms. LaFave, you are out of
your mind".
Now let's turn to the real heart of this essay.
Most people don't worry about metaphysical idealism or radical skepticism. But
a lot of people worry about ethical subjectivism.
Subjectivism in ethics is really just another example of the same
confusion about "subjective" and "objective".
The subjectivist says that because people have feelings about ethical
matters, claims about ethical matters themselves must be
subjective and therefore merely matters of opinion, and therefore
not liable to adjudication by reason or other objective methods.
In other words,
nobody has "better" (more objective) views about ethical matters than anyone else.
A similar debate exists in the contemporary art world, because of the same
confusion about subjectivity and objectivity.
Nowadays, some people say that no work of art is better than any other. The Campbell's
Soup logo is art; a pile of rocks or dog poop is art; the Aurora Borealis is art. Why?
Because whether or not something is art is a "subjective" matter. Philosophers cringe.
Heres one way to solve the problem, proposed by the
philosopher John Searle.
We should distinguish two kinds of objectivity:
metaphysical objectivity, and
epistemological objectivity.
We also should distinguish two kinds of subjectivity:
metaphysical subjectivity, and
epistemological subjectivity.
Remember the distinction between
metaphysics and epistemology?
Metaphysics consists
of arguments and counterarguments about what we should call "real" or what we should say
"is" or "has being". "Is free will real?" is a metaphysical question. In metaphysics,
something exists objectively if its existence
does not depend on its being experienced. For example, Antarctica and the
Eiffel Tower exist objectively. They exist whether or not anyone has experienced them.
Many realities are real in this way.
Something
exists metaphysically subjectively, by contrast,
if its existence depends on its being
experienced — like a headache, or how Bourbon tastes to you.
A particular headache ceases to exist if the person experiencing
the headache stops feeling it. Many realities are real in this way, too — still real, just real in a different way.
Now, you might be thinking your headache is a metaphysically objective event, in the sense that
your headache is just your brain state, and your brain state is potentially public and measurable.
Or, you might say that your headache is metaphysically objective in the sense that
it exists as an event in the history of the world; it is part of the stream of history just like any
other event.
I agree. Your headache IS a metaphysically objective event in these senses.
[1]There's currently an extremely interesting
debate raging in philosophy over the metaphysical significance of qualia.
The issue is whether or not qualia refute materialism (the metaphysical position that everything
is ultimately "stuff"). Do qualia exemplify non-material realities?
Some philosophers, e.g., Frank Jackson and David Chalmers, think so. Back